The principle of Counter-Closure embodies the widespread view that when a proposition is believed solely as the conclusion of single-premise deduction, it can be known only if the premise is also known. I raise a problem for the compatibility of Jason Stanley's Interest-Relative Invariantism (IRI) with Counter-Closure. I explore the landscape of options that might help Stanley resolve this tension and argue that a trilemma confronts Stanley: he must either (i) renounce a key intuition that lies at the foundation of his view; or (ii) admit into his epistemology an IRI-specific novel brand of Gettier case; or (iii) abandon Counter-Closure.</p
In a recent article [1], Charles Cross applies Lewisian counterfactual logic to explicate and evalua...
Certain puzzling cases have been discussed in the literature recently which appear to support the th...
One challenge for moderate invariantists is to explain why we tend to deny knowledge to subjects in ...
The view that knowledge-yielding single-premise deductive inference must proceed from a known premis...
Interest-Relative Invariantism (IRI hereafter) is the view that a person’s practical interests encro...
David Eaton and Timothy Pickavance argued that interest-relative invariantism has a surprising and i...
According to Interest-Relative Invariantism, whether an agent knows that p, or possesses other sorts...
The focus of this paper is the prima facie plausible view, expressed by the principle of Counter-Clo...
Interest-relative invariantism conjoins the interest-relativist thesis that knowledge depends in par...
In defending his interest-relative account of knowledge, Jason Stanley relies heavily on intuitions ...
Is it harder to acquire knowledge about things that really matter to us than it is to acquire knowle...
In this essay, I shall briefly present Epistemic Contextualism (EC), Invariantism and Interest- Rela...
Thomas Blackson argues that interest-relative epistemologies cannot explain the irrationality of cer...
The recent literature on knowledge from non-knowledge (KFNK) has been focused on deductive inference...
In defending his interest-relative account of knowledge in Knowledge and Practical Interests (2005),...
In a recent article [1], Charles Cross applies Lewisian counterfactual logic to explicate and evalua...
Certain puzzling cases have been discussed in the literature recently which appear to support the th...
One challenge for moderate invariantists is to explain why we tend to deny knowledge to subjects in ...
The view that knowledge-yielding single-premise deductive inference must proceed from a known premis...
Interest-Relative Invariantism (IRI hereafter) is the view that a person’s practical interests encro...
David Eaton and Timothy Pickavance argued that interest-relative invariantism has a surprising and i...
According to Interest-Relative Invariantism, whether an agent knows that p, or possesses other sorts...
The focus of this paper is the prima facie plausible view, expressed by the principle of Counter-Clo...
Interest-relative invariantism conjoins the interest-relativist thesis that knowledge depends in par...
In defending his interest-relative account of knowledge, Jason Stanley relies heavily on intuitions ...
Is it harder to acquire knowledge about things that really matter to us than it is to acquire knowle...
In this essay, I shall briefly present Epistemic Contextualism (EC), Invariantism and Interest- Rela...
Thomas Blackson argues that interest-relative epistemologies cannot explain the irrationality of cer...
The recent literature on knowledge from non-knowledge (KFNK) has been focused on deductive inference...
In defending his interest-relative account of knowledge in Knowledge and Practical Interests (2005),...
In a recent article [1], Charles Cross applies Lewisian counterfactual logic to explicate and evalua...
Certain puzzling cases have been discussed in the literature recently which appear to support the th...
One challenge for moderate invariantists is to explain why we tend to deny knowledge to subjects in ...