The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an implicit assumption of risk neutrality with respect to life duration. To overpass this limitation, we extend the theory to a simple variety of nonadditively separable preferences. The enlargement we propose is relevant for the evaluation of life-saving programs: current practice, we estimate, puts too little weight on mortality risk reduction of the young. Our correction exceeds in magnitude that introduced by the switch from the notion of number of lives saved to the notion of years of life saved
A choice model based on utility in each of a sequence of prospective future health states permits us...
This paper makes explicit the links between preferences over lotteries on length of life and interte...
It is often asserted that individual willingness to pay to reduce mortality risk is greater among in...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an impli...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an impl...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on the assumption that individ-uals are risk neu...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an impli...
This paper shows the poor capacity of the additively separable life-cycle model to fit empirical val...
The 1980s marked the first decade in which use of estimates of the value of life based on risk trade...
The standard model of intertemporal choice assumes risk neutrality towards the length of life: under...
This paper introduces a life-cycle model where impatience, instead of being driven by an exogenous d...
James Broughel wants to break the link between the willingness-to-pay principle embodied in the valu...
In protecting safety, health, and the environment, government has increasingly relied on cost-benefi...
There are no explicit markets for mortality risk reduction. An individual cannot purchase ‘‘mortalit...
Although the value of reducing mortality risks and that of reducing life year losses are closely rel...
A choice model based on utility in each of a sequence of prospective future health states permits us...
This paper makes explicit the links between preferences over lotteries on length of life and interte...
It is often asserted that individual willingness to pay to reduce mortality risk is greater among in...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an impli...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an impl...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on the assumption that individ-uals are risk neu...
The standard literature on the value of life relies on Yaari’s (1965) model, which includes an impli...
This paper shows the poor capacity of the additively separable life-cycle model to fit empirical val...
The 1980s marked the first decade in which use of estimates of the value of life based on risk trade...
The standard model of intertemporal choice assumes risk neutrality towards the length of life: under...
This paper introduces a life-cycle model where impatience, instead of being driven by an exogenous d...
James Broughel wants to break the link between the willingness-to-pay principle embodied in the valu...
In protecting safety, health, and the environment, government has increasingly relied on cost-benefi...
There are no explicit markets for mortality risk reduction. An individual cannot purchase ‘‘mortalit...
Although the value of reducing mortality risks and that of reducing life year losses are closely rel...
A choice model based on utility in each of a sequence of prospective future health states permits us...
This paper makes explicit the links between preferences over lotteries on length of life and interte...
It is often asserted that individual willingness to pay to reduce mortality risk is greater among in...